3.1. The Definition of the Riemann-Stieltjes Integral#
Let \(f\) and \(\alpha\) be real-valued functions on \([a, b]\). Assume \(\alpha\) is bounded. We say \(f\) is Riemann-Stieltjes integrable with respect to \(\alpha\) on \([a, b]\) if there exists a number \(A\) such that for any choice of \(\varepsilon > 0\), we can always find a partition \(P_\varepsilon\) of \([a, b]\) such that for any partition \(P\) finer than \(P_\varepsilon\), \(P \supseteq P_\varepsilon\), and for any list of representatives \(T\) of \(P\), the Riemann-Stieltjes sum satisfies
The number \(A\) is denoted by \(\int_a^b f \dif \alpha\) or more verbose, \(\int_a^b f(x) \dif \alpha(x)\), and is referred to as the (value of) Riemann-Stieltjes integral (of \(f\) w.r.t. \(\alpha\) on \([a, b]\)).
In Apostol’s definition [Apostol, 1974], the function \(f\) is assumed to be bounded. This assumption is made because if \(f\) is unbounded, the integral is bound not to exist. Consequently, Apostol chose not to explore integrals of unbounded functions, excluding them from his definition.
However, for educational purposes, we aim to demonstrate explicitly that the integral does not exist when \(f\) is unbounded. Therefore, we modify the definition to allow \(f\) to be unbounded and subsequently prove the non-existence of the integral.
If \(f\) is unbounded, then \(f \notin \mathfrak{R}(\alpha)\) on \([a, b]\).
Proof. We shall prove by contradiction. Assume, on the contrary, \(f \in \mathfrak{R}(\alpha)\) on \([a, b]\) and \(\int_a^b f \dif \alpha = A\). Then there exists a partition \(P = \{x_0, \ldots, x_n\}\) of \([a, b]\) such that for any list of representatives \(T\) of \(P\),
Let \(T_0\) be a particular list of representatives. Because \(f\) is unbounded on \([a, b]\), there exists \(j \in \{1, \ldots, n\}\) such that \(f\) is unbounded on \([x_{j-1}, x_j]\). It then follows that we may choose a point \(t_j^\prime \in [x_{j-1}, x_j]\) such that
Let \(T^\prime\) be constructed by replacing the \(j\)-th point \(t_j\) with \(t_j^\prime\) in \(T_0\). We have
It then follows that
This results in a contradiction with (3.1).